Nietzsche Redux And The Tyranny Of The Incoherent

“God is dead.” – Nietzsche

“Nietzsche is dead.” – God

Suitable for men’s room graffiti, we know.

Still.

We made quite a study of philosophy in our youth.  We cannot improve on Kierkegaard’s assessment of such an undertaking:

It is now about four years ago that I got the notion of wanting to try my luck as an author. I remember it quite clearly; it was on a Sunday, yes, that’s it, a Sunday afternoon. I was seated as usual, out-of-doors at the cafe in the Fredricksberg Garden. I had been a student for half a score of years. Although never lazy, all my activity nevertheless was like a glittering inactivity, a kind of occupation for which I still have a great partiality, and for which perhaps I even have a little genius. I read much, spent the remainder of the day idling and thinking, but that was all it came to.

So there I sat and smoked my cigar until I lapsed into thought. Among other thoughts I remember these: “You are going on,” I said to myself, “to become an old man, without being anything, and without really undertaking to do anything. On the other hand, wherever you look about you, in literature and in life, you see the celebrated names and figures, the precious and much heralded men who are coming into prominence and are much talked about, the many benefactors of the age who know how to benefit mankind by making life easier and easier, some by railways, others by omnibuses and steamboats, others by the telegraph, others by easily apprehended compendiums and short recitals of everything worth knowing, and finally the true benefactors of the age who make spiritual existence in virtue of thought easier and easier, yet more and more significant. And what are you doing?” Here my soliloquy was interrupted, for my cigar was smoked out and a new one had to be lit. So I smoked again, and then suddenly this thought flashed through my mind, “You must do something, but inasmuch as with your limited capacities it will be impossible to make anything easier than it has become, you must, with the same humanitarian enthusiasm as the others, undertake to make something harder.” This notion pleased me immensely, and at the same time it flattered me to think that I, like the rest of them, would be loved and esteemed by the whole community. For when all combine in every way to make everything easier, there remains only one possible danger, namely, that the ease becomes altogether too great; then there is only one want left, though it is not yet a felt want, when people will want difficulty. Out of love for mankind, and out of despair at my embarrassing situation, seeing that I had accomplished nothing and was unable to make anything easier than it had already been made, and moved by a genuine interest in those who make everything easy, I conceived it as my task to create difficulties everywhere.

In the 20th century at almost any university, even majoring in philosophy, you could escape any acquaintance at all with Kierkegaard (not that any sane person would want that); but it was impossible to escape from at least some familiarity with Nietzsche.

So Thus Spake Zarathustra and Beyond Good and Evil present themselves at some point, and the economy of expression afforded by aphorisms becomes a Thing,

Nietzsche had to be rehabilitated about the time we were engaged in our period of “glittering inactivity” ( late middle-to-late 20th century) because he had been so popular with Nazis.  Apparently this rehabilitation has accelerated and deepened in the time since, for as mainstream bellwether Wikipedia notes, later “scholars” have maintained that his apparent Nazi simpatico ideas were all a posthumous distortion by his demented, anti-semitic sister.

This is, to put it mildly, not plausible.  The “Ubermensch” is a central idea in Nietzsche’s thought.  Same for the “will to power”.  These are, you know, obviously Nazi friendly ideas.

And what else can we say about those central ideas? The ubermensch flows directly from an uncritical adoption of macro-evolution, a relatively new concept in Nietzche’s time, and of course an intellectual fad that lingers into the 21st century.  The argument is that the ubermensch is “…a goal humanity can set for itself…” and “…the creator of new values…” which is otherwise just a tad problematic in a post-modernist new age where everything before has been rejected and trashed.  You have to replace it with something, right?  Otherwise there’s nothing but nihilism.

But then that’s repeating ourselves.  Nothing but nihilism.  Get it?

So in order to reject the natural collapse into nihilism from this (frankly) silly musing about a “new [uber] man” – a bizarre, school boy fantasy better consigned to comic books than regarded as a serious contribution to western thought – we sanitize and over-complicate the thought and – again – blame Nietzsche’s horrible sister for the later affinity with Nazism.

But if you’re going to take the idea seriously – we don’t, but others do – it’s a natural fit both to nihilism and Nazism.  No way around that.  Nietzsche himself was said to have greatly feared the descent into the former as a consequence of his “theory”.  Post modernist Nietzsche fans should contemplate that for a change.

The “will to power“?  Let’s stipulate: it can be, lamentably, an accurate description and predictor of human behavior and to some extent the way the world works in general. Absent the phrase itself, the idea hardly originated with Nietzsche.  His contribution, rather, was to elevate the will to power as the highest principle of morality:  to be embraced, not resisted:

To speak of just or unjust in itself is quite senseless; in itself, of course, no injury, assault, exploitation, destruction can be ‘unjust,’ since life operates essentially, that is in its basic functions, through injury, assault, exploitation, destruction and simply cannot be thought of at all without this character. One must indeed grant something even more unpalatable: that, from the highest biological standpoint, legal conditions can never be other than exceptional conditions, since they constitute a partial restriction of the will of life, which is bent upon power, and are subordinate to its total goal as a single means: namely, as a means of creating greater units of power. A legal order thought of as sovereign and universal, not as a means in the struggle between power complexes but as a means of preventing all struggle in general perhaps after the communistic cliché of Dühring, that every will must consider every other will its equal—would be a principle hostile to life, an agent of the dissolution and destruction of man, an attempt to assassinate the future of man, a sign of weariness, a secret path to nothingness.

Intellectually, this is tediously familiar.  On the practical level, however, it is horribly fascinating:  we are enjoined to conduct ourselves and to order our lives in a manner so intellectually repugnant that in over two thousand years before Nietzsche not a single philosophical thinker of note had even seriously considered it.  We are to reject reason itself as mere emotional self-justification, the will to power dressed up as rational argument.  2+2=4 not because it does, but because in our insatiable desire for power we want it to.

Nietzsche was revolutionary indeed, but we don’t mean that as a compliment.

The decades long rehabilitation of Nietzsche has  apparently included the revelation – at least it’s a revelation to us – that although a scholar of ancient Greek and Latin he explicitly denigrated Parmenides and extolled Heraclitus:

Nietzsche’s philosophy, while innovative and revolutionary, was indebted to many predecessors. While at Basel, Nietzsche offered lecture courses on pre-Platonic philosophers for several years, and the text of this lecture series has been characterized as a “lost link” in the development of his thought. “In it concepts such as the will to power, the eternal return of the same, the overman, gay science, self-overcoming and so on receive rough, unnamed formulations and are linked to specific pre-Platonics, especially Heraclitus, who emerges as a pre-Platonic Nietzsche.” The pre-Socratic thinker Heraclitus was known for the rejection of the concept of being as a constant and eternal principle of universe, and his embrace of “flux” and incessant change. His symbolism of the world as “child play” marked by amoral spontaneity and lack of definite rules was appreciated by Nietzsche.  From his Heraclitean sympathy, Nietzsche was also a vociferous detractor of Parmenides, who opposed Heraclitus and believed all world is a single Being with no change at all.

How telling.  Where to begin?

Let’s leave the details out for a moment and bring out the broad brush to paint with.  Parmenides leads to Socrates and Plato, then of course to Aristotle, and together these can rightly be termed the foundation of western thought and even the foundation of western civilization, which later became Christian but always preserved the connection to these pre-Christian figures.

Heraclitus, on the other hand, although certainly known, was also a curiosity and a reject in western thought.

Ideas have consequences.  Ugh.

The difference is not complicated.  Heraclitus was exclusively empirical in approach, and Parmenides was exclusively rational.  Put another way, Heraclitus accepted sensory input as the only reality, and Parmenides rejected sensory input as unreal entirely.

Heraclitus and Parmenides could not have been further apart.

For more than two thousand years, though, western thought more or less starts with Parmenides and rejects Heraclitus.  Then around 1870 Nietzsche does the opposite.  What does it mean to do this?

As we have alluded to before, in posts and in comments and without purporting to take sides (although ultimately we do take sides but that’s not relevant right now), the belief in God is rational, but in order to be rational requires some level of rejection of the empirical, duh, because God is unseen.  Not as much rejection as Parmenides would have it, we note, but then it would be fair to describe the historical progression from Parmenides to Socrates to Plato and then to Aristotle as a gradual accommodation between the rational and the empirical, an accommodation that is possible if you start with Parmenides and reject Heraclitus but is impossible if you do the opposite.

Which is to say that if you embrace Heraclitus and reject Parmenides you will necessarily conclude that God is dead, just as Nietzsche did, because the belief in God’s existence is grounded in reason (rationality) but refuted by empirical observation.

But an astute reader will surely see the irony here:  this is, quite obviously, an entirely  rational process.  It is a simple syllogistic formulation:

Everything real is empirically observable.

God is not empirically observable.

Therefore God is not real.

The effort to elevate the empirical over reason by way of a syllogism, in other words, promptly self destructs.

If you go with Parmenides, on the other hand, the existence of a God becomes possible even though it is not empirically justified and can be seen as mandatory.  Because natural reason.*

So our ancestors in thought put Heraclitus behind them about the 3rd century B.C. and that’s where he stayed and that’s where he belonged, an historical and intellectual curiosity but ultimately unserious.

But then Nietzsche comes along and Heraclitus is reborn and becomes the new progenitor not of western thought and civilization, but rather post-western thought and civilization.  Which is a good way of putting it because this new worldview has no properties of its own; it exists solely as a negation of what came before it.

Kant no doubt thought it would be helpful to set forth a critique of pure reason, but in post modernism this is nothing but a fool’s errand.  To the post modernist, reason is not qualified to critique reason; that is the job of psychology:

Among his critique of traditional philosophy of KantDescartes and Plato in Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche attacked thing in itself and cogito ergo sum (“I think, therefore I am”) as unfalsifiable beliefs based on naive acceptance of previous notions and fallacies.  Philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre puts Nietzsche in a high place in the history of philosophy. While criticizing nihilism and Nietzsche together as a sign of general decay, he still commends him for recognizing psychological motives behind Kant and Hume‘s moral philosophy:

For it was Nietzsche’s historic achievement to understand more clearly than any other philosopher…not only that what purported to be appeals of objectivity were in fact expressions of subjective will, but also the nature of the problems that this posed for philosophy.

With apologies to Professor MacIntyre, it won’t do to call this an “historic achievement”.  Ascribing baser motives to what purport to be rational arguments has always been a common rhetorical device, and we mean “common” in the most derogatory sense:  intellectually low, a childish effort to one-up one’s interlocutor without engaging what is actually being asserted.  Reason maintains that propositions stand or fall on their own, and that whatever motives may be in play – and notably, it is not necessary to deny that that might be the case – are irrelevant.  Indeed the claim of reason is precisely that it inoculates against the infection of baser motives so as to better ascertain the truth of the matter.

It is therefore not surprising that those who deny this claim of reason would revert to the posture of Thrasymachus, but it is a bit startling to see this regression characterized as an historic achievement by those who should, and probably do, know better.  That is to say, Thrasymachus was a sophist.  In the modern sense.  Nietzsche’s revisionist intellectual somersaults are not historic achievements.

So at this point the question must be asked:  why do we pay any heed to Nietzsche at all?

Well, he was bereft of any genuine achievements, intellectual or otherwise, but that doesn’t prevent him from being post-modernism’s progenitor.  Indeed that is largely the point:  the meaninglessness of post-modernism begins with, and ought to begin with, a similarly meaningless “thinker”.  That doesn’t matter, because nothing matters.  That is the sole post-modernist principle, if you will, and it’s at work here.  Nietzsche matters precisely because he doesn’t.

Now.  Does all of this blather have any significance for the usual subject matter of this little blog-project of ours?

Oh, yes.

Nietzsche’s intellectual heirs came to dominate what we now call academia in the United States even before his unsavory (if posthumous) association with Nazism in the middle of the last century.  By the latter part of the 20th century this dominance had solidified into a monolith, particularly at the more prestigious universities, so much so that any hint of dissent from the foundational premises – atheism, disdain for religion, contempt for tradition, or at least any tradition pre-dating the degeneration into post-moderinism – became highly problematic.

It was impossible for his heirs, then, to discard Nietzsche – he was post-modernism’s intellectual father – so he had to be rehabilitated.  And that explains the revisionist work of Nietzsche “scholars”.

Law schools were especially vulnerable to intellectual fads and trendiness because, in the first place, in Nietzsche’s time they were brand new.  Law was one of the traditional “learned” professions, certainly, but “tradition”?  Meh.  We were busily forging the post-modern intellectual landscape out of the wreckage we ourselves had made of our intellectual past, and law schools were a trend.  A Thing.

Holmes and Nietzsche were contemporaries, but separated by language, culture and the Atlantic Ocean.  Yet how similar in outlook they were.  Talk about your weltgeist.

So Holmes gravitates towards eugenics (“…three generations of imbeciles are enough…”) during his much longer life and Nietzsche posthumously becomes a Nazi poster boy, and neither is at all surprising, given their common intellectual pedigrees, which is to say they didn’t have one, or maybe more properly speaking they had an anti-intellectual pedigree.

Anti-intellectualism has always been, and remains, an aberration in Europe; but in the United States it is part of our heritage.  European intellectuals could never fully embrace Nietzsche as much as American intellectuals have.  Europe has a vestigial loyalty to natural reason, even when they depart from it; America doesn’t.

Speaking of natural reason, the principle of non-contradiction is basic natural reasoning.  Unsurprisingly, Heraclitus rejected it and Parmenides surrendered to it, as any sane person will, at least to some degree.

So here’s a Europe-America contrast to illustrate the point.

Both Europe and America have a contentious political debate about abortion.  (We don’t want to run down that specific political road at the moment.  Just bear with us.)  Both have wound up “liberalizing” their legal treatment of abortion since the middle of the 20th century.  But in the US, some of the debate has involved the question of whether a human fetus is a “person”, because our SCOTUS in constitutionalizing the abortion issue in 1973 held that it wasn’t.  Which under the circumstances was, you know, a staggering intellectual error.  Europeans won’t truck with errors like that but Americans will because Nietzsche and Holmes and reason doesn’t matter and it’s all about what we want and who wins the struggle.  Will to power, doncha know.

So a few years later we are confronted with our error because the principle of non-contradiction will do that to you – and never mind that even at the time the SCOTUS made its ruling no less an abortion-favorable state than New York still dealt with abortion in its penal code under the heading “Abortion, Homicide and Related Offenses” – when some asshole shoots his pregnant girlfriend in the belly intending to kill the fetus and he succeeds and he’s charged with “murder”, but murder can only be of a “person” and so his lawyer says “what gives?” but the asshole is convicted and everyone is fine with that, including the SCOTUS, because non-contradiction is just an argument and arguments are cheap.

Just as with the definition of “person”, the most elementary natural reasoning is similarly dispatched in the courts all the time.  The examples are numberless.

So this is post-modernism applied. Quite simply, it is the tyranny of the incoherent.  It is madness, which is fitting because Nietzsche himself went mad at 44 and never recovered.  He lived out his days in the care of his mother and sister.  At one point he claimed to be the creator of the world.

If “the world” were to be redefined as the American legal profession and court system the claim would hardly be extravagant, though.

 

_____________________________________________________________________________________

* Nietzsche and post-modernism reject “natural reason”, of course, because they have to, but there’s no way to characterize this other than bizarre and perverse.  It would be a considerable understatement to say that we humans (and indeed animals) are utterly dependent upon natural reason every day; it’s more like every waking moment of every day.  Literally every single movement and every single thought, however trivial, is the product of it.

Advertisements

4 Comments

Filed under Uncategorized

4 responses to “Nietzsche Redux And The Tyranny Of The Incoherent

  1. Pickle Homer

    Lovely article. Very educational.

    Preface: I am only passingly educated about Nietzsche, but I am inquiring, effectively, about what Nietzsche meant by certain phrases, and if you find *all* interpretations of such phrases objectionable.

    Observation 1: You object to the usefulness and/or morality of Nietzsche’s “Will To Power” concept, by at least implying that the Will To Power should not be “embraced.”

    Observation 2: You object to Nietzsche’s claims that that morality is either subjective, or non-existent — on the basis of Nietzsche’s logic being in the tradition of Heraclitus’s empiricism rather than Parmenides’ rationalism. (this observation may be very wrong)

    Inquiry: If a person (let’s call him Bill) had a belief in a Parmenides-compliant moral code, and that moral code also has a substantial, generally-respected following (let us take, for example, Christianity, rather than believers in a flat Earth), would you object to Bill attempting to become as powerful as possible so that he may most effectively serve that moral code?

    Let us assume that Bill does not commit any obvious “ends justifies the means” atrocities, nor does he support them (eg. he’s not a Nazi advocating for killing or sterilization of any groups of people). Sorry, I know that’s vague, but hopefully you get the gist.

    Another way to ask the same thing: Is your objection to a “will for power” mostly because Nietzsche specifically advises power-without-purpose?

    Thank you for your time.
    picklehomer@gmail.com

    Liked by 1 person

    • Well, I think these are very good observations and questions. Getting right to the point, more or less.

      It’s been a while since this area was my daily study and inquiry, so I’m painting with a broad brush. One idea I was trying to get across with this post and the next one was the centrality of epistemological questions to western thought. The corollary being that these questions are difficult and involved and, as applied, highly consequential.

      So the epistemological hierarchy that emerged from antiquity and formed western thought for about 18 centuries was: empirical observations are governed by reason which in turn is governed by faith. Of course this was consistent with a theistic outlook, and inconsistent with – but not necessarily antagonistic towards – an atheist outlook.

      Because the prevalent theistic outlook was Christian the governing principle was love, not power. Love in the larger sense of “willing the good” of others, which in turn was bound up with the idea of virtue and the practice of virtue, which I think was conducive to increasingly peaceful and prosperous societies.

      In the wake of the Reformation, however, the epistemological hierarchy was increasingly challenged among intellectuals, especially among British thinkers of the 18th century like Hume and Bentham.

      This became a tendency towards an intellectual atheism that was more and more assertive and antagonistic towards the Christian faith. Because the epistemological hierarchy was like the foundational intellectual support structure for the Christian faith, this later intellectual trend inverted the epistemological hierarchy and came to be characterized by an increasingly radical empiricism.

      Of course, empiricism is ultimately incoherent and devoid of meaningful content. We had regarded “the reason” as governing empirical observation for the simple and self-evident reason that without it, sense impressions would be just so much random sensory noise.

      But the reason leads to the Christian God, and the Christian God leads to love and virtue.

      Nietzsche had this going for him: he faced squarely the consequences of rejecting all this. If love and virtue and willing the good is not a rational basis of human conduct and activity, what is? Observation without reason presents life as chaos and struggle for dominance.

      Of course this is incoherent as well. The reason, it turns out, is inescapable, because even this impoverished take on reality is an interpretation of empirical observations grounded in the reason.

      So perhaps the overall answer to your question(s) is that this intellectual trend, culminating in Nietzsche and to which I have deep objections, while not always murderous and incoherent in practice, is fundamentally and essentially both. Bill may not rape and murder today but he is just as likely to do that at any time because he refuses to recognize any principle that prohibits it.

      And as more specifically related to the blog project here, our “justice” system is exactly like Bill to the extent it has embraced radical empiricism and positivism intellectually, which is surely has. If there is any succinct way to sum up why we have so many wrongful criminal convictions, and why as a society we have such massive social and economic injustice, it is that. The institution that we have established to address such things not only refuses to do so, it does not even see such things as really being a problem.

      Like

  2. Pickle Homer

    Sorry, made a confusing error. “You object to Nietzsche’s claims that morality is either subjective, or non-existent” — I have two “thats” in the original post.

    Like

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s